Link Search Menu Expand Document

Notes and Slides

If the slides are not working, or you prefer them full screen, please try this link.

Notes

Convergent Validity

There is evidence that in older children (3-year-olds) and adults, the many varieties of false belief task all test for a single underlying competence (Flynn, 2006, p. 650; Wellman, Cross, & Watson, 2001). This is significant because there are many variants of false belief tasks which differ, for example, in whether participants are observers or interaction partners, and whether the false belief concerns a location, a category or even essentially involves numerical identity.

Do we also have good evidence that the various false belief tasks designed for infants all test for a single capacity?

‘implicit tasks suffer from a lack of convergent validity. Decades of research with explicit ToM tasks have shown that tasks that differ dramatically in surface features but share the same meta-representational deep structure, such as various false-belief and other meta-representational tasks [...], systematically converge. Proficiency in the different tasks ontogenetically emerges in tandem, and performance on the tasks is highly inter-correlated. By contrast, no systematic correlations have been found between the different types of implicit tasks, nor even within different tasks of the same type, all of which are designed to tap the same underlying construct.’ (Rakoczy, 2022)

Further, Poulin-Dubois & Yott (2017) find evidence for divergence.[1]

Disunity of Theory of Mind

Warnell & Redcay (2019) investigated a range of mindreading tasks with children of different ages as well as adults. They found

‘no clear structure underlying ToM emerged for any developmental period. [...] ToM tasks were minimally correlated in early childhood, in middle childhood, and in adulthood [...] ToM is a diverse construct that likely intersects with an array of other social and cognitive abilities

[...] The sophisticated understanding of others’ minds that underscores mature human social cognition may be an emergent property of varied skills combined with certain social contexts. Critical examination of how and why we measure ToM will offer insight [...] into cognition and behavior more broadly, as the lack of convergence among conventional ToM measures in the current study suggests that the best way forward in ToM research may be to take a step back.’ (Warnell & Redcay, 2019)

See also Beaudoin, Leblanc, Gagner, & Beauchamp (2020, p. 15):

‘The lack of theoretical structure and shared taxonomy in ToM definitions and its underlying composition impedes our ability to fully integrate ToM in a coherent and comprehensive framework linking it to various socio-cognitive abilities, a pervasive issue observed across the domain of social cognition.’

Happé, Cook, & Bird (2017) and Beaudoin et al. (2020) both offer taxonomies for Theory of Mind.

Glossary

mindreading : The process of identifying a mental state as a mental state that some particular individual, another or yourself, has. To say someone has a theory of mind is another way of saying that she is capable of mindreading.
According to an influential definition offered by Premack & Woodruff (1978, p. 515), for an individual to have a theory of mind its for her to ‘impute mental states to himself and to others’ (my italics). (I have slightly relaxed their definition by changing their ‘and’ to ‘or’ in order to allow for the possibility that there are mindreaders who can identify others’ but not their own mental states.)

References

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.
Balcombe, J. P. (2022). The Betrayed Fish: Reply to Oldfield. Journal of Animal Ethics, 12(1), 59–62. https://doi.org/10.5406/21601267.12.1.06
Beaudoin, C., Leblanc, É., Gagner, C., & Beauchamp, M. H. (2020). Systematic Review and Inventory of Theory of Mind Measures for Young Children. Frontiers in Psychology, 10.
Borg, E., Hansen, N., & Salomons, T. (2019). The Meaning of Pain Expressions and Pain Communication. In S. van Rysewyk (Ed.), Meanings of Pain: Volume 2: Common Types of Pain and Language (pp. 261–282). Cham: Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-24154-4_14
Bratman, M. E. (1985). Davidson’s theory of intention. In B. Vermazen & M. Hintikka (Eds.), Essays on davidson: Actions and events (pp. 13–26). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bratman, M. E. (1987). Intentions, plans, and practical reasoning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brozzo, C. (2021). Against the Distinction Between Intentions for the Future and Intentions for the Present. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4(58), 333–346.
Davidson, D. (1978). Intending. In Essays on actions and events (pp. 83–102). Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0199246270.001.0001
Fiske, A. P. (2020). The lexical fallacy in emotion research: Mistaking vernacular words for psychological entities. Psychological Review, 127(1), 95–113. https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000174
Flynn, E. (2006). A microgenetic investigation of stability and continuity in theory of mind development. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 24(3), 631–654. https://doi.org/10.1348/026151005X57422
Frankfurt, H. G. (1978). The problem of action. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(2), 157–162.
Halina, M. (2015). There Is No Special Problem of Mindreading in Nonhuman Animals. Philosophy of Science, 82(3), 473–490. https://doi.org/10.1086/681627
Happé, F., Cook, J. L., & Bird, G. (2017). The Structure of Social Cognition: In(ter)dependence of Sociocognitive Processes. Annual Review of Psychology, 68(1), 243–267. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-010416-044046
Harman, G. (1976). Practical reasoning. The Review of Metaphysics, 29(3), 431–463.
Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. Hillsdale, N.J: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Hobaiter, C., & Byrne, R. W. (2014). The Meanings of Chimpanzee Gestures. Current Biology, 24(14), 1596–1600. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2014.05.066
Howell, S. (1984). Society and cosmos: Chewong of Peninsular Malaysia. Singapore ; New York: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, R. R., & Cross, F. R. (2011). Spider Cognition. In J. Casas (Ed.), Advances in Insect Physiology (Vol. 41, pp. 115–174). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-415919-8.00003-3
Kalis, A., & Ometto, D. (2021). An Anscombean Perspective on Habitual Action. Topoi, 40(3), 637–648. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09651-8
Kano, F., Krupenye, C., Hirata, S., Tomonaga, M., & Call, J. (2019). Great apes use self-experience to anticipate an agent’s action in a false-belief test. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116(42), 20904–20909. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1910095116
Krupenye, C., Kano, F., Hirata, S., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2016). Great apes anticipate that other individuals will act according to false beliefs. Science, 354(6308), 110–114. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaf8110
Levy, Y. (2018). Why cognitivism? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 48(2), 223–244. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2017.1345207
Liu, M. (2022). The polysemy view of pain. Mind & Language, X(X). https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12389
Meristo, M., Strid, K., & Hjelmquist, E. (2016). Early conversational environment enables spontaneous belief attribution in deaf children. Cognition, 157, 139–145. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.08.023
Nagel, J. (2012). Intuitions and Experiments: A Defense of the Case Method in Epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3), 495–527.
Oldfield, R. G. (2022). You Can’t Betray a Fish: One Reason Eating Fish May Cause Less Harm Than Eating Cows. Journal of Animal Ethics, 12(1), 51–58.
Pika, S., & Bugnyar, T. (2011). The use of referential gestures in ravens (Corvus corax) in the wild. Nature Communications, 2(1), 560. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms1567
Poulin-Dubois, D., & Yott, J. (2017). Probing the depth of infants’ theory of mind: Disunity in performance across paradigms. Developmental Science, n/a-n/a. https://doi.org/10.1111/desc.12600
Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(04), 515–526. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00076512
Rakoczy, H. (2022). Foundations of theory of mind and its development in early childhood. Nature Reviews Psychology, 1(4), 223–235. https://doi.org/10.1038/s44159-022-00037-z
Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action: Elementary structures of practice and practical thought. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Vail, A. L., Manica, A., & Bshary, R. (2013). Referential gestures in fish collaborative hunting. Nature Communications, 4(1), 1765. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms2781
Velleman, D. (1989). Practical reflection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Warnell, K. R., & Redcay, E. (2019). Minimal coherence among varied theory of mind measures in childhood and adulthood. Cognition, 191, 103997. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2019.06.009
Wellman, H., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory of mind development: The truth about false-belief. Child Development, 72(3), 655–684.
Westra, E. (2021). Folk personality psychology: Mindreading and mindshaping in trait attribution. Synthese, 198(9), 8213–8232. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02566-7

Endnotes

  1. There are, however, studies which find a relation between performance on tasks suitable for infants and tasks used with older children (for example, Meristo, Strid, & Hjelmquist, 2016). ↩︎